Saturday, May 4, 2013

Structuration theory and empirical research




Over the past few years, particularly since the publication of The Constitution of Society, people in a diversity of fields have made use of concepts drawn from structuration theory in pursuing empirical inquiries. Areas in question include the study of stratification, organizations, educational systems, processes of urbanism, state forms, traditional communities, gender and ethnic divisions, mass media, legal systems, and others besides. I have been pleased, although also rather surprised, by the number and proliferation of such endeavours. On the other hand, on the whole I do not feel overly sympathetic towards the ways in which most authors have employed my concepts in their work. Most often, this is because they have tried to import the concepts I developed en bloc into their research, seemingly imagining that this will somehow lead to major methodological innovations. I have never believed this to be a sound approach, which is one of the main reasons why in The Constitution of Society, I emphasized that the theory should be utilized only in a selective way in empirical work and should be seen more as a sensitizing device than as providing detailed guidelines for research procedure.


While many have attempted to employ my perspective in a direct way in empirical study, others have taken a more negative stance. In other words, they have argued that structuration theory provides few or no useful pointers to the conduct of empirical work. An example is a lengthy review by Thrift.11 Writing about the chapter in The Constitution of Society in which I relate structuration theory to problems of empirical investigation, Thrift says that he finds this discussion 'deeply disappointing5. He sees my attitude as altogether too qualified, arguing that the theory 'should have a considerable amount to say . . . about the conduct and methods of research'. The disappointment comes from my not having delivered goods which it seemed to Thrift that the enterprise I have undertaken could reasonably be expected to convey.

Gregson's contribution to this volume contains some parallels to Thrift's view, although the conclusions she draws are different. Concentrating her attention on the same chapter in The Constitution of Society referred to by Thrift, she finds the connections I draw between structuration theory and the empirical research unconvincing. They lack, she says, 'the degree of specification required for empirical work' (p. 240). It is all very well to be told that all social research involves an ethnographic moment, that lay members of society are skilful and knowledgeable, or that one must have a sensitivity to how action is co-ordinated across time and space; but these are too far removed from the groundwork of empirical research to be of any value in guiding it. The various examples of research work which I refer to in the chapter in question were all carried out without any need for the concepts which, as it were, I have foisted upon them. Picking up my emphasis upon ontology rather than epistemology, Gregson concludes that the concepts connected with structuration make up a 'second-order theory', concerned 'with conceptualizing the general constituents of human society' and distinct from 'first-order theory', which generates concepts that apply directly to specific empirical settings.

I agree with some aspects of what Gregson has to say, but not with others. In my view, we should recognize what might be called the relative autonomy of theory and research. Theoretical thinking needs in substantial part to proceed in its own terms and cannot be expected to be linked at every point to empirical considerations. The more encompassing or generalized a set of theoretical notions is, the more this is the case. Empirical work, on the other hand, cannot proceed in the absence of abstract concepts or theoretical notions, but these are necessarily drawn upon selectively and cannot be ever-present. The category 'empirical work' is very large, moreover, and covers numerous different sorts of inquiries. Some types of research have local, descriptive objectives, while others attempt more to explore explanatory hypotheses. Research responds to contextualized inquiries, and one of the main errors of those who formulated canons of research under the aegis of logical empiricism was to regard the only 'authentic' work as that which sets up specific hypotheses, derived from theory, and proceeds to seek to test them. The 'how?' and 'why?' questions which social research answers are too variegated to be subsumed within so neat a scheme.

Similarly, 'theory' covers a multiplicity of endeavours. The main tenets of structuration theory, as Gregson rightly points out, are intended to apply over the whole range of human social activity, in any and every context of action. Other concepts I have coined or worked with, such as 'the commodification of space' or 'surveillance mechanisms', have somewhat more substance, in the sense in which they direct attention to specific processes or aspects of concrete social systems. However, I would not myself draw a distinction between 'first-order' and 'second-order' concepts. Theory is also contextual. Some concepts and theoretical schemes are more abstract than others, and those involved in the general suppositions of structuration theory do indeed operate at a high level of abstraction. But even the most abstract concepts interlace, or can be connected with, more specific ones. This is as true of the notions of structuration theory as of any other generalized standpoint in the social sciences.

One might if one likes make a rough distinction between 'theory', as a generic category, and 'theories', where the latter term refers to explanatory generalizations. Structuration theory clearly belongs to the first of these types rather than the second. As I have pointed out in The Constitution of Society, the significance of'theories', as compared to 'theory', can easily be exaggerated. Some writers are prone to pour scorn upon the tendencies of the social sciences to produce abstract conceptual schemes at the expense of explanatory generalizations-theory, rather than theories - but I do not think such complaints for the most part are justified. No doubt many arid conceptual webs are spun, but so also are many vapid or uninteresting generalizations proposed. 'Theory', in my view, is at least as important in the social science as theories; I would not accord one logical priority over the other.

I do not agree with Gregson's contention that structuration theory is largely irrelevant to empirical research. Being abstract and generalized, and being 'theory' as contrasted to a set of 'theories', it is necessarily at some distance from particular research projects. I would still maintain today the position I set out in the chapter previously referred to in The Constitution of Society, which I would see as more relevant to the conduct of empirical research than Gregson allows. Structuration theory is not intended as a method of research, or even as a methodological approach. The concepts I have developed do not allow one to say: 'henceforth, the only viable type of research in the social sciences is qualitative field study'. I have an eclectic approach to method, which again rests upon the premise that research enquiries are contextually oriented. For some purposes, detailed ethnographic work is appropriate, while for others archival research, or the sophisticated statistical analysis of secondary materials, might be more suitable. But I do think the framework of structuration theory both provides concepts relevant to empirical research and also warns against the pitfalls of some types of research procedure or interpretations of research results.

The objective of my discussion in The Constitution of Society was to demonstrate these points, and I need only briefly recapitulate them here. In some part my remarks concerned the logic of research; to some degree they were directed towards illustrating how the concepts of structuration theory 'look' when examined in relation to concrete research tasks. For instance, it is a logical feature of social research, following from the double hermeneutic, that all research endeavours have an ethnographic or 'anthropological' aspect to them. Since this is a logical point, by definition it does not disclose anything directly which is an option for a researcher; it sets out what all social investigation, without exception, involves. Yet it would be wrong to say that it is without direct relevance to the conduct and interpretation of research. Thus someone who believes she or he is dealing only with 'hard facts' - say in the shape of a mathematical analysis of quantitative variables - might both misconstrue what those 'facts' are and other conclusions to be drawn from them, if the point is ignored. Cicourel demonstrated this effectively enough some while ago in his discussion of the use of official statistics in social research.

In my discussion I looked at several pieces of research, of a heterogeneous character. The point, as I believe I made clear, was not to demonstrate what research 'inspired by structuration theory' would be like; it was, as I put it at the time, to work out 'the logical implications of studying a "subject-matter" of which the researcher is already a part' and to elucidate 'the substantive connotations of the core notions of action and structure'. Looking at an investigation of a directly ethnographic kind - Willis's study - 1 sought to show that some of the main virtues of the research derive from the fact that the researcher was sensitive to some of the key emphases formally elaborated in structuration theory. I also wanted to show (something Willis was also very conscious of) that small-scale, detailed ethnographic work can show us a great deal about institutional reproduction. In relating the empirical observations to such reproduction, moreover, no functionalist assertions of any kind are required. The other examples I used were designed to show how structural constraint, contradiction and institutional change could be examined in research contexts involving quite different empirical procedures from that adopted by Willis. I sought to demonstrate that the analysis of structural constraint presumes an empirically grounded interpretation of motivation; that, per contra, the empirical study of contradiction cannot just proceed on the level of motivated action, but presumes the study of structural constraint; and that the effective empirical analysis of institutional change means grasping the relations between reflexively monitored transformations and unintended consequences of action.

Structuration theory is a broad perspective upon the study of action, structure and institutions. Its relation to empirical research is much the same as that of competing perspectives or schools of thought. Robert K. Merton's codification of functionalism, as set out in his book Social Theory and Social Structure, for example, offers an overall orientation to social analysis, but scarcely provides recipes for empirical research. As Bernstein shows, many of the presuppositions of structuration theory stand in direct contrast to the framework which Merton established, and which served as an overall orientation for a whole generation of sociologists. I should be happy indeed were my writings to have anything approaching the influence exerted by those of  Merton. The main point in this context, however, is that the status of the two endeavours is approximately the same. Merton tried to establish close ties between the more abstract principles he endeavoured to set up and other theoretical and empirical work upon which he became engaged. The same also applies in my case, as I indicated in the opening paragraphs of this reply. There may be no 'structurationist programme' of research, but I can certainly sketch what I would take to be some principal empirical concerns upon which social research should be focused.

Let me first of all, however, connect some of the general emphases of structuration theory with empirical work by 'reversing the coin' from the style of presentation I adopted in the chapter in question in The Constitution of Society. In that chapter, as mentioned, I analysed certain aspects of concrete research projects in order to provide an empirical illumination of some of the basic elements of structuration theory. It might be helpful here if I briefly proceed in the opposite fashion, indicating how social research might proceed when consciously informed by the structurationist outlook.

Let us suppose we wished to study marriage relationships, and the break-up of marriage, in a number of communities of varying socio-economic levels. Our main interest is in the nature of marital relationships and in the origins and consequences of marital separation. Information is obtained from various sources: fieldwork study in two or three of the communities in question, in-depth interviews and the use of local archival materials. How might some of the notions of structuration theory be used as sensitizing devices in the pursuit of such a research inquiry?

The prime underlying orientation, both of the planning of the investigation and the interpretation of its results, would be towards examining the complexities of action/structure relations. This is a mixed process of observation and decoding. As an operational principle of research, what structuration theory suggests is not that we should seek to categorize or classify the rules and resources involved in a given area of social conduct, but rather that we should place the emphasis squarely upon the constitution and reconstitution of social practices. Investigating 'structure' in the structurationist sense is more than simply looking for patterns in how the behaviour of some individuals connects with that of others. It means delving into the subtle interplay between the intractability of social institutions and the options they offer for agents who have knowledge, but bounded discursive awareness, of how those institutions work.


We would ground the research, therefore, in an attempt to examine stasis and change in the reproduction of institutionalized practices. The 'marriage relationship' is a set of expectations held by partners about each other, sanctioned within the overarching framework of the legal system. These expectations 'enter into' the relationship, but they are only constituted in and through the regular habits, strategies of behaviour and so forth which partners follow, inside and outside the relationship itself. Consider, for instance, the question of how far the marital relationship itself is strongly emphasized in social interaction, or alternatively is fairly well submerged in other kin ties and obligations. This is best studied through showing how regularized day-to-day, or more periodic, activities serve consistently to remake - or perhaps help unmake - wider kin ties. Thus one instance of this, in matrilocal marriage, might be the practice which women have of popping in to see their mothers on a regular and routine basis. Where such a practice exists, it expresses informal conventions which are reconstituted in its very enactment. The practice may be relatively 'untheorized' by those concerned, since it is simply accepted as what is 'done' in the area. Alternatively, a greater range of skilful, strategic thinking may be involved where the practice for one reason or another has come under pressure. Thus if husbands now expect wives to spend more time in the home, caring for and improving it - or if they expect wives to take on paid employment - various more calculative and 'thought-through' modes of sustaining daughter-mother intimacy might have to be devised.

'Structure' here is embedded in practice (or, in actuality, in a diverse, fragmentary and sometimes contradictory series of practices) in which it is recursively implicated. Study of the 'everyday' or the 'day-to-day' forms a basic part of the analysis here, many seemingly trivial or mundane features of what people do being the actual 'groundwork' of larger-scale institutions. It is in the durability of institutions that we look to discern the structural properties of systems of relationships in which people's activities are engaged. In empirical terms, this immediately means an 'opening out' across time and space. In other words, it necessitates a historical or developmental perspective and a sensitivity to variations of location. In the case of the hypothetical research project, this would involve far more than just a gross comparison of communities in terms of variations according to geographical situation or class composition. It would mean - ideally at least - a thoroughgoing study of the contextualities of institutionalized patterns of interaction. For instance, the pattern of daughters popping in to see mothers might be temporally sedimented as tradition and spatially organized via locales in which a considerable degree of gender segregation is maintained - through a combination of matrilocality and a male 'pub and club' pattern.

Localized forms of practice can be 'mapped' institutionally within wider social systems in terms of what I have sometimes called 'structural sets' (or simply 'structures' in the plural). Studying structural sets is best understood as examining the articulation of institutions across time and space. Structural sets are formed through the mutual convertibility of rules and resources in one domain of action into those pertaining to another. In the case of the putative research project, a number of such articulations could be diagnosed and analysed. For instance, marriage relationships, gender and labour markets are connected through certain general conditions of mutual convertibility which 'lead into' the situated practices in which agents are involved. As discussed previously, gender cannot be seen as simply a number of characteristics possessed by individuals, but rather has to be understood as structured via rules and resources specifying connotations of sexual difference. Gender divisions represent differential 'convertible currency' in labour markets, since the institutionalized practices which prevail in the economic domain mostly favour men rather than women. Labour market characteristics articulate with the domain of family life, which in turn helps restructure gender. Insofar as these connections span the wider societal system, they provide for similarities of behaviour and experience which in some part transcend regional and class differences. Structural sets are implicated in what in The Constitution of Society I called circuits of reproduction: feedback systems by means of which structural sets and structural principles are grounded and regrounded in institutionalized practices 'stretching' across time-space regions. Studying concretely just how the interconnections between marriage relationships: gender: labour markets: marriage relationships are 'played out' means seeking to identify how these 'conversions' between institutional areas are reproduced in actual
conduct.

Conditions of change are built into reproduction circuits, especially in the context of modern societies, in which they are in some part reflexively organized. Suppose we wish to investigate why there are increasing levels of separation and divorce in the communities in the research study. How might we analyse this? Many factors can of course influence processes of social change. But in empirical work, as in theoretical reflection, it is crucial to try to identify how unintended consequences interlace with the forms of knowledge which, both on practical and discursive levels, actors bring to bear upon the contexts of their behaviour. In the research with which we are concerned, this task could be approached on various levels. Like so many other areas in modern societies, the institutional milieux of marriage and divorce have become highly mobilized reflexively - via, for example, the regular revision of divorce laws and other legal provisions, which are understood by everyone to have to 'correspond' in a general way to alterations in conditions of social life. These alterations are monitored sociologically, this knowledge filtering down to the day-to-day modes of behaviour which people follow in marriage and other aspects of their personal lives. What results are shifting forms of awareness involved in the practices that actually express marriage relationships, and in the objectives which individuals seek to realize in or through those relationships. Difficult as such a task may be, it would be incumbent upon the research to capture these interconnections empirically.

Let me generalize from these observations. What would a structurationist programme of research for modern social science look like? First, it would concentrate upon the orderings of institutions across time and space, rather than taking as its object the study of'human societies'. The term 'society' may well be so engrained in sociological discourse as to be ineradicable, and I do not feel it necessary to avoid using it. However, where we speak of'a' society, we have to be fully aware that this is not a 'pure social form', but a politically and territorially constituted system. It is one mode of 'bracketing' time and space among others, that bracketing process itself being the primary object of study in social science.

Second, a structurationist programme would analyse social systems in terms of shifting modes of institutional articulation. Every social system, no matter how small or ephemeral, or large scale and more permanent, gains its systemic qualities only through regularities of social reproduction. The ways in which such regularities - which consist of social practices - are organized in and through the behaviour of contextually located actors have to be subjected to empirical investigation. Modes of institutional articulation - across time and space - are the 'building-blocks' of time-space distanciation. Third, such a programme would be continuously sensitive to the reflexive intrusions of knowledge into the conditions of social reproduction. This has nothing intrinsically to do with contrasts between the small scale and large scale, or between 'micro' and 'macro' analysis. We can see this from the fact that world-wide connections are today reflexively monitored - as, for example, in the case of investment decisions taken by the leaders of the giant corporations.

Fourth, a structurationist programme would be oriented to the impact of its own research upon the social practices and forms of social organization it analyses. This is an aspect of reflexivity which involved us in the various levels of critique noted earlier. The problems it raises are formidably complex, but are quite central to the 'self-understanding' of the social sciences in the current era.

To my mind, however, the empirical implications of structuration theory have to be pursued primarily through the introduction of considerations - concerned with particular types of social system and their transformation - which are not part of the theory itself. These are bound up with the themes I set out at the beginning, and this is an appropriate point at which to close the circle in ending my commentary upon the contributions to this book. The chief focus of contemporary social science - although it is a very broad one - has to be upon analysing the shattering impact of modernity, against the backdrop of the limited usefulness of the traditions of thought which we have inherited in the social sciences. Such study demands serious theoretical reappraisals, combined with the pursuance of a diversity of empirical inquiries. Do we now live in a world which has lurched away from earlier trends of social and cultural development expressed in modernity? Or do we now live in a period shaped by the radicalizing of modernity: the first time at which modernity has become globalized (which is my view)? How should we best examine the increasing intrusion of distant events into the intimacies of personal life? What are the social textures emerging from altered modes of the co-ordination of time and space, as this affects overlapping types of social system? How should we conceive of, and further elaborate, the critique of ideology and moral critique in the face of the massive transformations of our time? Momentous questions, certainly, but I cannot see how anyone working in the social sciences today – whether engaged in carrying out empirical research 'on the ground', or pursuing more theoretical reflection - can avoid them.



SOURCE : Social theory of modern societies: Anthony Giddens and his critics (1994) / edited by David Held and John Thompson. © Cambridge University Press 1989
 

Kindly Bookmark this Post using your favorite Bookmarking service:
Technorati Digg This Stumble Stumble Facebook Twitter
Your adsense code goes here

0 komentar:

Post a Comment

Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.

 

| SOCIAL STUDIES-Qu News © 2013. All Rights Reserved |Template Style by Social Studies-Qu News | Design by Fer Bas | Back To Top |